3
Philosophical Review Naturbetrachtung und Naturerkenntnis im Altertum: Eine Entwickelungsgeschichte der antiken Naturwissenschaften by Franz Strunz Review by: W. A. Heidel The Philosophical Review, Vol. 13, No. 5 (Sep., 1904), pp. 586-587 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2176873 . Accessed: 15/05/2014 17:50 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Review. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 91.229.248.139 on Thu, 15 May 2014 17:50:31 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Naturbetrachtung und Naturerkenntnis im Altertum: Eine Entwickelungsgeschichte der antiken Naturwissenschaftenby Franz Strunz

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Naturbetrachtung und Naturerkenntnis im Altertum: Eine Entwickelungsgeschichte der antiken Naturwissenschaftenby Franz Strunz

Philosophical Review

Naturbetrachtung und Naturerkenntnis im Altertum: Eine Entwickelungsgeschichte derantiken Naturwissenschaften by Franz StrunzReview by: W. A. HeidelThe Philosophical Review, Vol. 13, No. 5 (Sep., 1904), pp. 586-587Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical ReviewStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2176873 .

Accessed: 15/05/2014 17:50

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extendaccess to The Philosophical Review.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 91.229.248.139 on Thu, 15 May 2014 17:50:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 2: Naturbetrachtung und Naturerkenntnis im Altertum: Eine Entwickelungsgeschichte der antiken Naturwissenschaftenby Franz Strunz

586 THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW. [VOL. XIII.

hint in the account given by M. Piat. The very notion of potentiality receives scant justice, being noticed, as it were in passing, in connection with other allied conceptions. Regarded also from the historical point of view, as it concerns either logical or physical science, the notion is of extraordinary interest. Another case in point is the idea of qualitative change (alolwatg). When one surveys the thought of the Middle Ages, which is Aristotelianism writ large, one is astounded at the fruitfulness of this conception. One has only to refer to two among the many aspects under which it reappears in order to make clear its significance. One is the idea of transmutation, met in alchemy in its firm belief in a phi- losopher's stone. The other is the theological doctrine of transsubstan- tiation. What cognizance does M. Piat take of this conception ? He passes over it with only a citation from Aristotle, enumerating it with the other forms of change (rusa#oA) in the chapter on Mo/ion (pp. 96 if).

I have said enough to characterize the book in hand; it is, in spite of its bulk, a meager though fairly faithful restatement in outline of the Aristo- telian philosophy from the point of view of Aristotle himself. It casts no glance behind or before to take in the relation of the system or of its several doctrines to the larger movement of thought which we call the history of philosophy. It may well be doubted whether such a book was greatly needed. W. A. HEIDEL.

IOWA COLLEGE, GRINNELL.

Naturbetrachtung und Naturerkenninis im A/ker/um: Eine Entwicke- /ungsgeschich/e der antiken Naturwissenschaf/en. Von FRANZ STRUNZ.

Hamburg und Leipzig, Verlag von Leopold Voss, 1904.-PP. Viii, i68.

This book contains six chapters: I. Introduction; II. The Theoretical Basis of the Conception of Nature among the Oriental Peoples; III. The Practical Study of Nature among the Oriental Peoples; IV. The Concep- tion and Philosophy of Nature in Classical Antiquity; V. Scientific Prac- tice in Classical Antiquity and in its Decline; VI. Epilogue.

The most marked difference between the present work and others of similar scope that have recently appeared is that its main concern is with science rather than with philosophy. One thinks naturally of such books as Gomperz's Grechische Denker and Benn's The Phiiosoyhy of Greece; yet the fields occupied by the three works is by no means the same. The scheme adopted by Dr. Strunz is that of a parallel account of the theo- retical and the practical aspects of the conscious relations of the ancients to nature. The subject is one to awaken curiosity, and the Introduction is such as to raise expectations of great results. I regret to say that one's high hopes are somewhat rudely dashed as one proceeds with the reading of the book.

The Introduction contains some striking aphorisms on the proper method to be observed in writing the history of thought. With much that is there said the present reviewer finds himself in the heartiest agreement. But

This content downloaded from 91.229.248.139 on Thu, 15 May 2014 17:50:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 3: Naturbetrachtung und Naturerkenntnis im Altertum: Eine Entwickelungsgeschichte der antiken Naturwissenschaftenby Franz Strunz

No. 5.] NO TICES OF NE W B O OKS. 587

there appears in the body of the book no serious effort to apply the method; hence it will be of no avail to transcribe what we must regard merely as fine phrases.

Few things would be more cordially welcomed by scholars than an honest attempt, -however much questioned its results in detail, -fully to state and intimately to relate the two series of ascertainable facts: first, the prac- tical knowledge had by mankind at various epochs of the phenomena and processes of nature, as manifested in the arts, sciences, and handicrafts, as well as in the social institutions, such as the domestic, the political, the religious; second, the theoretical evaluation and interpretation of life and nature, as displayed in mythology, religion, morals, and philosophy. It was not precisely this, but something like this, that Dr. Strunz contem- plated. What he has actually done is this. He has with commendable diligence collected from many sources, -good, bad, and indifferent, much matter that may serve another more competent to deal critically with it, when the right man undertakes to set ancient theory and practice in things pertaining to nature into clearer relations. Dr. Strunz himself has done little or nothing in this direction, leaving the two series of facts quite unrelated.

While the work before us is, in a sense, a rudis indiges/aque moles, it is not a useless book; indeed, there are here and there portions worthy of most diligent perusal. Students of ancient thought will find little of value in the brief characterization of the philosophical opinions of the Greeks ; but on the side of science and technology, where the author's interest manifestly centers, there is much to stimulate thought.

In his treatment of the oriental peoples, Dr. Strunz quotes freely from the less technical recent literature, giving the results which may be regarded as on the whole at present received; in the earlier part of the history of occidental thought he is not always so fortunate, quoting with approval sometimes from the briefer handbooks, sometimes from recent literature, statements which it were wiser to ignore. On the other hand, his previous occupation with Theophrastus Paracelsus has familiarized him with certain phases of the influence exerted by Aristotelianism on medieval thought, which he brings out clearly and forcibly.

I dare not finish this brief notice of the book without saying that its author appears to recognize in some degree its shortcomings, and holds out a hope of amendment in the future. In his brief preface he says, " I Vielleicht wird das, was vorliufig stark aphoristische Akzente trdgt, spdter breiter und tiefgrUndiger ausgearbeibet werden." W. A. HEIDEL.

IOWA COLLEGE, GRINNELL.

Theotihrastus Paracelsus, sein Leben und seine PersOnlichkeif. Ein Beitrag zur Geistesgeschichte der deutschen Renaissance. Von FRANZ STRUNZ.

Leipzig, Diederichs, 1903. -PP. 127.

The labors of Dr. Karl Sudhoff have thrown much light on the life and character of Paracelsus, the famous natural-philosopher and professor of

This content downloaded from 91.229.248.139 on Thu, 15 May 2014 17:50:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions